1. Modal Realisms and Modal Epistemology
According to the semantic realist about modality, there are modal truths: as opposed, say, to all modal discourse being systematically false, as the error theorist has it, or non-factual, as the projectivist has it. We require an epistemology for modality only if semantic realism holds, so semantic realism is presupposed for the purposes of this article. Semantic realism about modality is a necessary but non-sufficient condition for ontological realism about it. For the ontological realist the distinctively modal element to the modal truth is grounded in mind-independent reality (rather than, for example, being grounded merely in convention).1
Much current work in the epistemology of modality focuses on metaphysical modality, taking after Kripke’s approach to a posteriori necessity. For Kripke, we know the necessary a posteriori by modus ponens inference from an a priori major premise and an empirical minor premise. For example, following the exposition of Hale (1996, p. 492):
If a chemical stuff has a given chemical formula then it has that chemical formula of necessity.
Water is the chemical stuff with chemical formula H2O.
Water is necessarily H2O.
It is the truth, rather than the necessity, involved in the necessary a posteriori that is known a posteriori. The a posteriority of the conclusion is the result of “spill-over” from the empirical minor premise. The modal major premises, which Elder (2004, p. 5) dubs “template truths”, are held to be known a priori (e.g., Kripke 1971, p. 88). Rationalist accounts of modal epistemology entail that at least some modal knowledge is essentially a priori.2 However, we may be tempted, with Ellis (2001), Mišcevič (2003) and perhaps Elder (2004), to be realists about natural necessity but opponents of a priori modal knowledge construed rationalistically.3 The main aim of this article is to suggest that such temptation should probably be resisted. A positive modal epistemology for ontological realism about the modal is likely to be a rationalist one. In this section, some varieties of realism and anti-realism about the modal are explained. Some rationalist theses in the epistemology of modality are outlined and some putative combinations of ontological realism about the modal with anti-rationalism are summarized. Sections 2 and 3 argue against two such combinations. It is concluded, minimally, that those who contend that ontological realism about modality can be combined with the wholesale rejection of modal rationalism have not established their view. Moreover, it is difficult to see how they might do so.
In the context of the epistemology of modality, an epistemic conception of the distinction between rationalism and empiricism is of primary concern. Rather than being about the origins of our ideas, this conception of the distinction concerns epistemic priority. An item of propositional knowledge, p, is epistemically prior to an item of propositional knowledge, q, if and only if knowledge that q depends on knowledge that p and knowledge that p does not depend on knowledge that q.
Weak rationalism about the modal results from the combination of the following theses. First, there are items of modal knowledge and (at least) some of them depend on some items of a priori modal knowledge. Second, for some of those items of a priori modal knowledge, no item of a posteriori knowledge is epistemically prior. The weak rationalist’s first thesis can be embraced by non-Quinean empiricists. It is the second thesis which provides the distinctively rationalist element to weak rationalism.4 The second thesis does not require that the relevant a priori modal knowledge is epistemically prior to the relevant a posteriori modal knowledge, but it precludes the a posteriori modal knowledge from being epistemically prior to the a priori modal knowledge. The Quinean empiricist will reject the second thesis, partly on the basis that there is no a priori knowledge. Empiricist foundationalists like Ayer (1950) will reject it on the grounds that empirical knowledge is epistemically prior to a priori modal knowledge. For the rationalist foundationalist, like Descartes, some a priori knowledge has epistemic priority over all other items of propositional knowledge. Weak rationalism is compatible with, but does not entail, rationalist foundationalism.
Strong rationalism about the modal claims that there are items of modal knowledge and that for every item of modal knowledge, p, there is some item of modal knowledge, q, such that knowing p requires a priori knowledge of q. When knowing that p requires a priori knowledge that q, then either the epistemic priority is in a q-to-p direction or else q and p are one-and-the-same item of knowledge. Strong rationalism debars there from being any item of modal knowledge which lacks a basis in the a priori. For the strong rationalist, there can be no exclusively empirical process resulting in modal knowledge. Some extra-empirical knowledge is required whenever a modal truth is known.
Kripke (1971; 1980) set out to refute the claim, central to the orthodox logical positivist approach to modality, that the necessary and the a priori are co-extensive.5 Kripke takes the modal major premises in arguments to modal knowledge a posteriori to be a priori. If Kripke accepts that for some of those items of a priori modal knowledge, there is no item or set of items of a posteriori knowledge epistemically prior to the a priori modal knowledge, then he is (at least) a weak rationalist.6 Strong anti-rationalism rejects weak rationalism. I distinguish between two ontologically realist, strongly anti-rationalist strategies concerning the modal. One is based on confirmationism about the modal; the other, on the appeal to the explanatory purchase of the modal.7
Confirmationism tries to ward off epistemological worries by providing an empirical account of how we can tell the difference between what must be and what merely is. The claim is that knowledge of metaphysical modality does not require the a priori. Elder (1992; 2004) is what I am calling a “confirmationist”. The strategy of the appeal to the explanatory purchase of the modal, on the other hand, claims that modalising has explanatory content with respect to the empirical world. If either strategy works, then a key motive for rationalism, namely the thesis that the modal is empirically empty, is undercut.8
Before proceeding further, let us review some philosophical theories concerning matters ontological and epistemological. We will focus, in particular, on the relationships between these theories.
We are concerned with the three ontologically realist approaches. The ontological realist may hold that a model of knowing which has it that all our knowledge is derived via our causal interaction with the world is more epistemologically suspect than modality. That is to say, it may be claimed that we can justifiably be more certain that we know that a given modal claim is true than that we know to be true an epistemological theory which brings our claim to modal knowledge into doubt or which, if our claim to knowledge were true, could not explain its truth.9 By the lights of global rationalism, knowledge of at least some aspects of at least some of our concepts is, as a matter itself of real necessity, fundamentally a priori. Modal rationalists take it that such knowledge includes knowledge of some of the modal truths. On one form of account, for example, the deeming of certain modal propositions as true is taken to be characteristic of having the cognitive capacities constitutive of understanding the conceptual contents of those propositions.
The ontologically realist strategies in modal epistemology are cotenable so long as no one of them is taken to extend to all modal knowledge. Only in its strong form does rationalism fail to be cotenable with any of the other ontologically realist strategies. For the philosopher who wishes to provide an epistemology for ontological realism about modality there appears to be no pathway which does not involve dependence upon the a priori. In the next two sections I consider, and reject, two such putative pathways. Moreover, considerations are offered which suggest that the exponents of these pathways do not succeed in executing their ambition to provide philosophies of modality which do not require modal rationalism.
2. Confirmationism
The confirmationist takes it that the distance between the empirical and the modal that the modern philosopher typically assumes is an exaggeration. Contrary to the view that we can observe only what is the case and never what must be, the advocate of confirmationism has it that knowledge of de re modality can be wholly empirical. On this view, observation can provide us with defeasible evidence of necessity. Confirmationism is inconsistent with McGinn’s claim (1981, p. 81) that the modal transcends what can empirically be verified. The falsehood of McGinn’s claim, however, is insufficient for the falsehood of weak modal rationalism.
Elder (2004, p. 22) claims that “there is an empirical test for essentialness”.10 Moreover, Elder (2004, p. 38) holds that “conclusions about the properties essential to nature’s kinds and stuffs and phenomena” can properly be gleaned “strictly from what we learn by experience”. Although he is an ontological realist about the modal, Elder (2004, pp. 38-39) rejects rationalism about “template truths” (i.e., the modal major premises in modus ponens arguments to necessary a posteriori conclusions), seeing his modal epistemology as an alternative to such rationalism. Modal scepticism and modal anti-realism are often motivated by appeal to the apparent lack of harmony between realist suppositions about modality and a causal account of knowledge. So, modal scepticism and epistemologically motivated modal anti-realisms can be offset if we can provide an epistemology for modality that does not go beyond the epistemological parameters internal to those views. This perspective is an element in the approach of Elder (1992; 2004).
Elder sets up the following dilemma. If the realist’s ultimate explanation of the difference between necessarily and contingently true universal generalisations is that a necessarily true universal generalisation holds in all possible worlds, then “there is not the least reason to suppose we are reliable at detecting” such necessities (1992, p. 317). If the difference itself is held to be primitive, the realist is seemingly left with no way of distinguishing between what counts as evidence for the modalised generalisation and what counts as evidence for the non-modal generalisation, except “an undiscussable difference -one apprehended by some form of pure intuition” (1992, pp. 317-318; compare 2004, p. 6). Elder’s way out is to seek to provide an empirical test for distinguishing between essential and accidental generalisations, where the former are understood to involve “those sorts of necessity which, as everyone agrees, we are entitled to believe in only if we do more than just entertain them in our minds -only if we also do empirical research” (1992, p. 318).
Against rationalism about “template truths”, Elder offers a cursory attack on the appeal to intuition and an alternative, confirmationist, epistemology. The only rationalist model of knowledge of template truths Elder discusses is that of intuition, construed as direct intellectual insight, which he dismisses as “fanciful” (2004, p. 6). From this, along with Elder’s remark (2004, p. 3) that conventionalism provides the only “developed” modal epistemology to rival his own, it may be surmised that he thinks little of modal rationalism, in which the appeal to intuition plays a major role.11 In dismissing the appeal to intuition, Elder’s anti-rationalist point is not, it seems, that appealing to rational intuition as evidence for template truths is appealing to rational intuition at the wrong stage in the process of acquiring modal knowledge a posteriori. Rather, it is that the supposition that intuition has any role to play in knowledge of essence and natural necessity is at best gratuitous.
Elder employs the notion of contrariety in proposing his empirical test for essentialness:
First, we must establish that Ks are in fact uniformly characterized by properties in a certain cluster -say, by properties f, g, and h. Subsequently, we must discover that items generically akin to Ks, and differing from Ks by bearing some property (say, f ′ ) contrary to a property that Ks uniformly have, likewise uniformly bear properties contrary to others of the properties Ks uniformly have (the generically similar kind will have, say, g ′ and h ′). I call this test “the test of flanking uniformities”. It is the test which [. . . ] we [. . . ] rely on for judging that Ks have f essentially [. . . ], it is the test we should rely on. (2004, p. 23)
The proper contraries of a property, such as the atomic number of an element, are those, such as the atomic numbers of other elements, with which that property is commensurable but distinct (2004, p. 28). The identity of a property “consists at least partly in its contrasting, to the various (but commensurable) degrees it does, with its own proper contraries” (2004, p. 29). Elder appears, at least on the surface, to rely upon a priori intuition in his account of contrariety: “It seems utterly unbelievable that weighing 3.2 kg might have been compatible with weighting 28 kg, or that it might have been only slightly different from weighing 28 kg. Could red conceivably have been quite similar to green?” (Elder 2004, p. 31).
This talk of seeming might appear to be precisely the kind of intellectual seeming that Bealer (1987; 2002) classifies as a priori intuition. However, on the presumption that Elder (2004) retains the epistemological views of Elder (1992), things are not as the passage above makes them seem. Elder (1992) holds that knowledge of property contrariety is itself a variety of purely empirical knowledge of metaphysical modality. If knowledge of property contrariety is purely empirical, then Elder’s appeal to it is not in tension with his contention that knowledge of essentialist necessity is purely empirical. If, on the other hand, knowledge of property contrariety requires a priori intuition, then an epistemology for essentialist necessity that appeals to knowledge of property contrariety cannot be a purely empirical epistemology. Property contrariety is far from being a modally innocent notion. F and G are contrary properties only if it is impossible for there to be any entity which simultaneously instantiates F and G. Now if knowledge of contrariety is a type of modal knowledge that is a necessary condition for knowledge of essentialist necessity more generally (such as the necessity involved in characterising the natures of individuals, stuffs and laws) and if it requires (an at least weak) rationalism, then Elder’s position that knowledge of essentialist necessity is strictly empirical becomes unstable. Let us consider, then, the plausibility of Elder’s view that knowledge of property contrariety is purely empirical. Elder anticipates the objection that such knowledge is not purely empirical:
In defence of realism about all forms of necessity, I have sketched an empirical test for essentialness, and a parallel test for lawfulness [. . . ]. But in running either test we must rely on our ideas as to what properties are competitive with the one we suspect of being essential, or with the one we suspect of being lawfully linked to the instantiation of some further property [. . . ]. Some readers will suppose that these ideas are themselves far removed from empirical confirmation or disconfirmation. (Elder 1992, p. 330)
The discussion (1992, pp. 331-332) that follows this remark, however, shows that the readers Elder has in mind are of conventionalist, rather than rationalist, inclination. The sorts of properties Elder (1992; 2004) often uses as examples when discussing property contrariety are properties that are quantitatively specified. We have already seen one such example, from Elder (2004, p. 31), involving weight. Here is another:
There is excellent evidence that competitive with the having of the atomic number 79 is the having of atomic number 80, the having of 81, and the havings of all the others [. . . ]. For over the entire range of the physical elements, no two of these properties are present at any one element, and at least one is. (Elder 1992, p. 333)
What, though, is the real bearing of evidence here? It does not seem that Elder has made it at all clear. Moreover, the initial intuition that we are dealing with a priori incompatibility here (though not necessarily incompatibility of properties) would appear to be defensible, on the following grounds. If I have exactly two coins in my pocket then that is incompatible with my having exactly three coins in that very pocket. That incompatibility can be expressed, independently of the use of number concepts, as a truth of first-order logic, by translating the following sentence into first-order logic: it is not the case that I have both exactly two coins in my pocket and exactly three coins in the same pocket. Similarly, if an element has exactly 79 protons in its nucleus then that is incompatible with its having exactly 80. Again, that incompatibility can be expressed as a truth of first-order logic (though doing the translation would be a long and tedious task). That no element has both exactly 79 protons in its nucleus and exactly 80 is a first-order logical truth, so long as we allow our variables to range over elements. (The necessitations of these two logical truths, in turn, are theorems of the normal quantified modal logics.) If some of the property incompatibilities Elder considers relevant to essentialist necessity are logical truths, then (since his account of essentialist necessity in general rests on the idea of property contrariety) in order to support a strictly empirical account of essentialist necessity he requires an empirical construal of logical truth. Elder has not shown, and it is not clear as to how it could be shown, that knowledge of the sorts of (alleged) property contrariety to which his arguments appeal is strictly empirical, since his arguments crucially include the appeal to such quantitatively specified property contrarieties as the one just discussed.
Suppose, with Elder, that the template truths are known empirically. This supposition need pose, of itself, no threat to Peacocke’s contention that “any a posteriori premises in the ultimate justification for a piece of modal knowledge will not themselves be modal” (1999, p. 168). The rationalist may be giving a priori intuition a role that comes too late if the rationalist maintains that the template truths are know by a priori intuition. The supposition that the template truths are necessities a posteriori entails that any rationalist analysis would have to be applied at a level removed from the template truths themselves. That is, the rationalist’s analysis would apply to some modal major premise in an argument in which an a posteriori template truth is the conclusion. Peacocke makes the following observation about Heathcote (2001):
If I understand Heathcote’s position correctly, he holds that there can be fundamentally a posteriori knowledge of necessities. If there can be, there ought to exist (or at least it ought to be possible for there to exist) an a posteriori necessity whose grounds cannot be split up into propositions that are either modal and a priori, or a posteriori and nonmodal. I do not know of any such examples. (Peacocke 2001, p. 112)12
The template truths are not, I have suggested, genuine examples. At least, I have argued, Elder has not shown them to be genuine examples. If it is contended that essentialist necessities are known purely empirically, then some such examples must be produced.
3. Explanationism
The explanationist about modality denies a contention that frequently features in the reckonings of modal anti-realists, namely that, supposing that there are modal facts, they are not causally explanatory with respect to our knowledge of them. Mišcevič (2003) combines a realist´ view of modality with “causal explanationism” (2003, p. 5) about modal intuition. Mišcevič views modal knowledge as “´ prima facie” a priori (2004, p. 44) and “ultimately a posteriori” (2003, p. 28, fn. 4). Though Mišcevič does not explicitly engage with McGinn, his´ position is a challenge to McGinn’s claim that “we cannot represent modal facts as causally explaining our knowledge of them” (1981, p. 185). When we adopt knowledge acquired by sensory perception as the only sort of knowledge a causal account of knowledge can accommodate, McGinn’s claim seems obvious. No one holds that we so perceive the modal facts. Mišcevič, though, seeks to show that´ a causal account can also accommodate intuition, including modal intuition. Mišcevič combines epistemic naturalism with a modal conception of actuality. His hypothesis is that our modal intuitions track the deep modal structure of the world. We have the modal intuitions we have because of how nature has shaped our minds.13 Perhaps Mišcevič is right that our modal intuitions track modal reality due´ to our mental capacities having been shaped by a reality that is inherently modal. In order for intuitions to have evidential weight, however, more is required than the epistemic possibility that they track mind-independent reality. Rather, that they do so must actually be the case (and so it has to be metaphysically possible that they do so). But how are we to find out whether it is more than just an epistemic possibility that they do so?
Naturalism about intuition is discussed by Bealer (1987, pp. 323- 327). Bealer objects to naturalism by observing that “there is no independent reason to hold that intuitions that are just ‘hard-wired’ or that are just byproducts of efficient brain organization are tied to the truth” (1987, p. 326). Mišcevič’s position, however, is different´ to the naturalism about intuition Bealer is attacking. On Mišcevič’s´ view, modal reality causes our modal intuitions, through its having “shaped our mind design” (2003, p. 20). His position on the relationship between modal intuition and modal truth is in fact analogous to Bealer’s: modal intuition is a reliable indicator of modal truth. The main difference between Bealer and Mišcevič is that Bealer offers´ an avowedly rationalist account of why modal intuitions count as evidence whereas Mišcevič takes himself to be offering a naturalis-´ tic account. Mišcevič’s view, however, is based on an unsuccessful´ argument. In a move reminiscent of the indispensability argument in the philosophy of mathematics,14 Mišcevič (2004, p. 57; 2003, p. 21) writes that “The appeal to modal facts is indispensable for systematization and explanation of non-modal ones. Therefore, we should assume that [. . . ]. Modal facts exist [. . . ]. Causal processes indirectly carry information about deep modal structure.” Suppose that modalising is indispensable to our best science. From that, no realism about modality follows, whether semantic or ontological. While modalising may well be indispensable, it is a big step from that to the claim that there are modal facts and a further step still to the claim that we require an ontologically realist account of modal facts. I believe that nothing in the naturalist programme can secure these further claims. Indeed, I think, with Quine, that naturalism is opposed to them. In mathematics we quantify over numbers and the naturalist may claim, with Quine and Putnam, that since this quantification is indispensable to our best science we are committed to the existence of numbers. In science we modalise, but for a good analogy to hold with the case of modality our best science would have to include indispensable quantification over modal facts. If the nouns “possibility” and “necessity” are, as traditional and modern modal logic take it, dispensable in favour of modal modifiers, or if our best science involves no quantification over alethic possibilities and necessities, then we have no good analogy with the indispensability argument in mathematics. In any case, Mišcevič’s view does not´ come close to establishing that modal knowledge is ultimately a posteriori. The claim that our modal intuitions have natural causes does not entail a strong empiricism about the epistemic status of modal claims. If modal reality shapes our minds in such a manner that our modal intuitions are reliably tied to the modal truth, then, assuming externalism about justification, our modal intuitions can give rise to justified beliefs even if we do not know that modal reality so shapes our minds. The hypothesis that modal reality shapes modal intuition is not itself a modal hypothesis. The claim that the hypothesis is metaphysically possible is a modal hypothesis. But we don’t need to know whether the hypothesis is metaphysically possible in order to have some modal knowledge. The truth of the hypothesis would, even if we were ignorant of it, be enough. Now the hypothesis is supposed to be supported, on Mišcevič’s account, by an argument´ to the best explanation (2003, p. 213) from “total empirical evidence at a reflective level”. This is why Mišcevič takes the hypothesis to´ be a matter for naturalistic inquiry. But even if that view of the status of the hypothesis is correct (which I believe it is not) this does not establish that modal knowledge is ultimately a posteriori. In order for it to do so, knowledge of the hypothesis would have to be epistemically prior to or epistemically on a par with, modal knowledge. That it is neither has just been shown.15 Weak rationalism is consistent with the provision of a causal explanation of modal intuition: all weak rationalism asserts is that there is a priori modal knowledge not epistemically dependent on any a posteriori knowledge. That weak rationalist thesis is safe from causal explanationism both insofar as causal explanationism is a genetic thesis and insofar as it is an epistemic thesis. Even if the reliability of modal intuition is a matter of naturalistically explicable “mind design”, this does not entail that modal intuitions are not ultimately a priori. Since causal explanationism about modal intuition does not establish that modal knowledge is ultimately a posteriori, it does not succeed in refuting weak modal rationalism.
4. Conclusion
We have considered two attempts to combine ontological realism about modality with a positive modal epistemology hostile to weak modal rationalism. In the case of Elder, the appeal to quantitatively specified property contrarieties has not been shown by him not to rest on the a priori. An account of such contrarieties has been provided which suggests that, if known at all, they are known a priori. The explanationist approach advocated by Mišcevič, involving the claim´ that we can view the modal facts as causally explanatory with respect to our modal intuitions, is, as it stands, explanatorily less satisfactory than a rationalist alternative and it does not establish a workable antirationalist case. I conclude that recent attempts to combine modal realism with opposition to modal rationalism fail. I conjecture that a viable positive epistemology for ontological realism about modality is likely to be in harmony with weak modal rationalism.16